Brian Holmes on Thu, 1 Nov 2001 19:54:13 +0100 (CET) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> Re: the myth of democracy |
I wonder how Ian Andrews feels, now that Kermit Snelson has "sided" with him in his critique of nik's original post on "the myth of democracy." Sometimes these discussions bring you uncomfortable acquaintances. The kind that cover up all the substantive arguments. Among the painfully reactionary bits of Snelson's post is this: "Most of the issues that have been raised on the streets over the past two years are technical and will require considerable scientific expertise to solve. Global warming? Sustainable agriculture in the developing world? Debt relief? Drug patents? ... Waving signs, chanting slogans and throwing a rock won't do a thing. Those who really care about these issues should pick one, develop real knowledge about it and become valuable to one of the many organizations that are actually working on it." Snelson doesn't seem to recognize that the huge international effort to begin doing something about global warming has been blocked by the democratic government of the United States. He affects not to realize that expert citizens' groups such as the Confédération paysanne, Greenpeace, Attac, the Council for Canadians, Jubilee 2000, Focus on the Global South, and hundreds of others large and small are in the streets precisely because their efforts to influence national governments and international bodies through typical citizens' tactics, moving from counter-expertise to petitions and lobbying, have been unsuccesful. He apparently has not read the interview with Nobel Prize winning economist Joseph Stieglitz, posted here on nettime - if he had, he would know that the former World Bank chief economist himself is in the streets when the Bank and the IMF meet, because he was unable, as an expert, to get them to change their policies. Snelson also doesn't realize that the groups I've cited, along with the hundreds of other citizens-and-experts that have merged into the "movement of movements," pretty much all switched over to the tactics of global convergence demonstrations involving direct action, after Reclaim the Streets and the Seattle DAN network, in particular, led the way. The citizens groups and the dissenting experts followed because those tactics appeared to do what electoral politics didn't, namely get some results or at least put the issues on the map. Nik quotes Negri and Hardt to say: "It is perhaps an exaggeration to characterize elections as an opportunity to choose which member of the ruling class will misrepresent the people for the next two, four, or six years, but there is certainly some truth in it too and low voter turnout is undoubtedly a symptom of the crisis of popular representation through electoral institutions." He could have quoted the economist Schumpeter, writing in the 40s, who established basically the same theory of electoral democracy as a means for the continuing reproduction of elite power. He could also have quoted Jean-Pierre Charbonneau, head of the Quebec National Assembly and founder of the Parlementary Conference of the Americas, who pointed out that the FTAA treaty being negotiated last April had never even been shown to the parliamentary representatives to whom the finer points of democratic representation are supposedly confided. There are real problems with what Charbonneau calls "executive democracy." That said, I don't just side with Nik. I think protest movements are all about productive disagreements. It is obvious to me that efforts to establish and improve democratic process have accompanied capitalism since its inception, resulting in the twentieth century in the creation of substantive systemic improvements like health and welfare systems, mass education systems, guaranteed vacations, minimum wage provisions, public cultural sectors, whatever environmental legislation there is, and so forth. Capitalism and democracy are both mutually supporting and antagonistic, that's the fundamental political paradox of modern times. That we are in a period where capitalism has got the upper hand is no reason not to continue working toward democratic ideals. In fact, I think the "counter-globalization movements" (Nik's excellent phrase) owe the beginnings of their success to the increased emphasis given to democracy after 1989, as the legitimating framework that was supposed to accompany capitalist globalization. Protest movements play on the critical gap between democratic ideals and capitalist reality. Precisely the gap that people like Snelson want to erase when they get rhetorical about "our enemies" who are "deploying 767s and anthrax against our families." The point of the us and them business is to urge "us" to "get real", i.e. quit protesting and support the status quo. No thanks Kermit. Given that "our enemies" may also turn out to be the American far right, I think I prefer to continue working with the democratic idealists and radical autonomists who pragmatically take to the streets. All the arguments I've dealt with so far just act to cover up the extremely interesting questions in Ian Andrews's post. Rather than condemning every facet of the recent protest movements without distinction, Andrews asks questions. He doesn't affirm that democracy only works in the frame of the nation-state; instead he takes the care to asks whether democracy is imaginable anywhere else. The point is to raise the question of democratic process. In the face of a declining commitment to social welfare on the part of neoliberal governments, he asks, "Who will take responsibility for the dispossessed, the economically discarded, the environment, world health, etc."? And then he says "we need some mechanism to do this." His complaint with the autonomists is that they are offering no universalizable mechanisms. And yet at the same time, his own arguments point to all the flaws in the currently available universals. He appeals to Marx as a philosopher who submitted his own thought to a process of constant critique, and he offers the idea that "universal suffrage, like the liberal democratic state, should not be regarded as an absolute ideal, the end of history, or the ultimate high point of civilization, but rather as part of the political toolkit we have at our disposal." No appeal to a clash of civilizations here. What it comes down to is that the supposedly democratic countries are in great need of fresh experiments with democratic process. The spread of mass education and the access to powerful communications systems have made obvious the democratic deficit of systems based on electoral representation. Andrews makes the point when he says that the needed mechanism for the assumption of social responsibilities "involves a number of strategies, including a rethinking of the concept of the state that radically distances it from paternalism, and that incorporates... the idea (from the liberal democratic state) of the separation of powers, and a multiplicity of channels (perhaps involving autonomous social actors)." The "perhaps" opens up the interesting part for the discussion at hand. The fact is that the autonomous movements are today among those who are experimenting with new forms of collective decision-making, i.e. new forms of democracy. Like Andrews, I get impatient with their denial of the need for universalizing mechanisms sedimented in enduring institutions - i.e., their denial of any form of state. But at the same time, I appreciate very much the way their tactical practice is calculated to produce democratic innovation by upsetting the immobilizing forces of the state bureaucracies and the exploitative powers of capitalist corporations. An important step forward could be made, at this point, if the autonomist groups could get their heads around the idea that their "anti-state idealism" is actually part of a radical democratic idealism. Democracy is very much about freedom, and very much about the autonomy of diverse social groups. In a period of experimentation with democratic process it is imaginable that spaces for the kinds of collective freedom that autonomist groups seek could be significantly enlarged. At the same time, only the other major ideal of democracy - equality - can ensure that freedom is not simply the privilege of the powerful, as it has been for the neoliberals. The difference between the neoliberals and the post-communist autonomists is sometimes hard to see, when you focus on the libertarian strand of thinking that they effectively share. But the differences in their practice are obvious. The autonomous groups seek an extension of egalitarian freedoms, or egaliberty, as Etienne Balibar says. And that isn't a myth. It's a social struggle that's been going on for a long, long time. Brian Holmes # distributed via <nettime>: no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a moderated mailing list for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@bbs.thing.net and "info nettime-l" in the msg body # archive: http://www.nettime.org contact: nettime@bbs.thing.net