Pit Schultz on Wed, 14 Jan 1998 02:18:29 +0100 (MET) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
<nettime> Latour, Bruno: On Actor Network Theory: A few clarifications 2/2 |
Building on the semiotic turn, ANT first brackets out society and nature to consider only meaning-productions; then breaking with the limits of semiotics without losing its tool box, it grants activity to the semiotic actors turning them into a new ontological hybrid, world making entities; b= y doing such a counter-copernican revolution it builds a completely empty frame for describing how any entity builds its world; finally, it retains from the descriptive project only a very few terms -its infralanguage- whic= h are just enough to sail in between frames of reference and grants back to the actors themselves the ability to build precise accounts of one another by the very way they behave; the goal building of an overarching explanatio= n -that is, for ANT, a centre of calculation that would hold or replace or ponctualise all the others- is displaced by the search for ex-plicitations, that is for the deployment of as many elements as possible accounted for through as many metalanguages as possible. . . . Now that the basic topological properties of networks have been sketched -second section- and that the basic ontological features of actors have bee= n outlined -section above- there is no difficulty in seeing that ANT is not about traced networks but about a network-tracing activity. As I said above there is not a net and an actor laying down the net, but there is an actor whose definition of the world outlines, traces, delineate, limn, describe, shadow forth, inscroll, file, list, record, mark, or tag a trajectory that is called a network. No net exists independently of the very act of tracing it, and no tracing is done by an actor exterior to the net. A network is no= t a thing but the recorded movement of a thing. The questions ANT addresses have now changed. It is not longer whether a net is representation or a thing, a part of society or a part of discourse or a part of nature, but what moves and how this movement is recorded. We cannot say that what moves inside networks are informations, genes, cars= , bytes, salutations, words, forces, opinions, claims, bodies, energy, etc. since ANT also wants to reconstruct nets before there is any distinction between what circulates inside and what keep them on track, so to speak, from the outside. Again, as I said at the beginning, the technical metaphor of networks is a latecomer for ANT and does not capture the tracing activity. No, what circulates has to be defined like the circulating object in semiotics of texts -especially scientific texts (Bastide, 1990). It is defined by the competence it is endowed with, the trials it undergoes, the performances it is allowed to display, the associations it is made to bear upon, the sanctions it receives, the background in which it is circulating, etc. Its isotopy -that is its persistence in time and space- is not a property of its essence but the result of the decisions taken through the narrative programs and the narrative paths. However, such a classic definition would limit ANT to the world of text and discourse. What happens when a circulating object leaves the boundary of a text? The traditionnal answer is that there is a yawning gap in between the text and the context. At the interface a dramatic trial is supposed to abruptly intervene through which the circulating object is assessed either by checking its referential fit or its social interest. Not for ANT which does not believe in this distinction since it has extended meaning productions to all productions. For ANT the gap is no more than a slight bump along the net; the yawn is an artefact caused by a previous divide between nature, society and discourse. For ANT there is on the contrary a continuity, a multiplicity of plugs, between the circulating objects in the text, the claims outside the text in the 'social', and what the actants themselves really do in 'nature'. The circulating object goes on circulatin= g and goes on getting its isotopy from what other actors do to it. 'Society' has the same net-like properties as the texts, and so has 'nature'. But it would be more accurate for ANT to say that these three categories are arbitrary cutting points on a continuous tracing of action, and still more accurate to show how these categories are themselves part of the many trials, and events, and ressources that are used along the paths to attribute 'textuality' or 'sociality' or 'naturality' to this or that actor= . They are part of what is distributed not part of what makes the distribution. There is no off-the-shelf word to describe this common movement. To say tha= t it is a generalized narrative path would immediately mean that texts are extended to everything; to say that it is a force, or an energy, or a gene, or a culture-gene would mean that everything would be naturalized including society and discourses; to say that it is a social interest or a social action or labor would extend society to nature and to texts. It is to get out of this essential difficulty that ANT played with a generalized symmetr= y (Callon, 1986) and made a principle of using whichever words are connoted i= n one of the former realm to describe the others, thus showing the continuity of networks and the complete disregard for the artefactual gaps introduced by prerelativist arguments. However this solution is rather tricky since it may combine all the misunderstandings -and this is indeed what happened to ANT, readers and users alike saying at once that it is a social constructivist argument, the return of naturalism or a typically French belief in the overall extension of texts... Which of course it is in a sense, but only in so far as ANT is the simultaneous rejection of naturalisation, socialisation and textualisation. ANT claims that these '(x)-lisations' have to be dissolved all at once and that the job is not done better if one of them gains hegemony or if the three are carefully circumscribed. All (x)-lisations are the filling in of what is 'in between' the networks, and which one is chosen or rejected makes no practical difference since nets have no 'in between' to be filled in. If chosing words for the network-tracing activity has to be done, quasi-objects (Serres, 1987) or tokens might be the best candidate so far. It is crucial for the definition of the term that what circulates and what makes the circulation be both co-determined and transformed. A ball going from hands to hands is a poor example of a quasi object since, although it does trace the collective and that the playing team would not exist without the moving token, the latter is not modified by the passings. Conversely, what I called the first principle of science studies (Latour: 1987) -that a claim is in the hands of others- is equally an approximation since it entails human locutors to begin endowed with hands and mouths who passes a claim without they themselves undergoing dramatic changes. As a rule a quasi-object should be thought of as a moving actant that transforms those which do the moving because they transform the moving object. When the toke= n remains stable or when the movers are kept intact, these are exceptional circumstances which have to be accounted for. This definition of what is a rule and of what are the exceptions, would be enough to tell ANT apart from all models of communications that, on the contrary, begin from well defined movers and moving objects and view obstacles to exchanges as so many exceptions to be explained. But another feature forbids any confusion of AN= T with human centered, or language-centered, or praxis-centered models. As a rule, what is doing the moving and what is moved have no specific homogeneous morphism. They can be anthropo-morphic, but also zoo-morphic, phusi-morphic, logo-morphic, techno-morphic, ideo-morphic, that is '(x)-morphic'. It might happen that a generative path has limited actants t= o a homogeneous repertoire of humans, or of mecanism, or of signs, or of ideas, or of collective social entities, but these are exceptions which should be accounted for (Latour, 1996c). . . . ANT is a powerful tool to destroy spheres and domains, to regain the sense of heterogeneity and to bring interobjectivity back into the centre of attention (Latour, 1994). Yet, it is an extremely bad tool for differentiating associations. It gives a black and white picture not a colored and contrasted one. It is thus necessary, after having traced the actor-networks, to specify the types of trajectories that are obtained through highly different mediations. This is a different task and the one that will make ANT scholars busy for a number of years to come. --------------------------------------------------------- References Wilda Anderson, Diderot's Dream, The Johns Hopkin's University Press, Baltimore, (1990). Malcolm Ashmore, The Reflexive Thesis. Wrighting (sic) Sociology of, Chicag= o University Press, Chicago, (1989). Fran=E7oise Bastide, 'The Iconography of Scientific Texts: Principle of Analysis', in M. Lynch et Woolgar S. (ouvrage dirig=E9 par), Representation= in Scientific Practice, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass, (1990), p. 187-230. Michel Callon, 'Some elements of a sociology of translation domestication o= f the scallops and the fishermen of St Brieux Bay', in J. Law (ouvrage dirig= =E9 par), Power, Action and Belief. A New Sociology of Knowledge?, (1986), p. 196-229. Michel Callon, John Law et Arie Rip, (ouvrage dirig=E9 par), Mapping the Dynamics of Science and Technology, Macmillan, London, (1986). Michel Callon et Courtial Jean-Pierre, Co-Word Analysis: a Tool for the Evaluation of Public, Report for the NSF grant PRA N=B085 12 982, Paris, (1989). Michel Callon, Jean-Pierre Courtial et Fran=E7oise Lavergne, La M=E9thode d= es mots associ=E9s. Un outil pour l'=E9valuatio des programmes publics de recherche. Etude pour la National Science Foundation, Ecole des Mines, Paris, (1989). Thomas P. Hughes, Networks of Power. Electric Supply Systems In the US, England and Germany, 1880-1930, The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, (1983). Gilles Deleuze, Diff=E9rence et r=E9p=E9tition, PUF, Paris, (1968). Gilles Deleuze et F=E9lix Guattari, Mille plateaux. Capitalisme et schizophr=E9nie, Minuit, Paris, (1980). Harry Garfinkel, Studies in Ethnomethodology, Prentice Hall, New Jersey, (1967). Algirdas Julien Greimas, On Meaning. Selected Writings in Semiotic Theory., University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, (1976). Thomas P. Hughes, Networks of Power. Electric Supply Systems In the US, England and Germany, 1880-1930, The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, (1983). Christian Jacob, L'empire des cartes. Approche th=E9orique de la cartograph= ie =E0 travers l'histoire, Albin Michel, Paris, (1992). Bruno Latour, Science In Action. How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society, Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass, (1987). Bruno Latour, The Pasteurization of France, Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass., (1988a). Bruno Latour, 'The Politics of Explanation: an Alternative', in S. Woolgar (ouvrage dirig=E9 par), Knowledge and Reflexivity, New Frontiers in the Sociology of Knowledge, (1988b), p. 155-177. Bruno Latour (1988c), 'A Relativist Account of Einstein's Relativity', Social Studies of Science, vol. 18, p. 3-44. Bruno Latour (1994a), 'On Technical Mediation';, Common Knowledge, vol. 3(2), p. 29-64. Bruno Latour (1994b), 'Une sociologie sans objet? Note th=E9orique sur l'interobjectivit=E9', Sociologie du travail, vol. 36(4), p. 587-607. Bruno Latour, 'Flat-Earthers and Social Theory', in M. Power (ouvrage dirig= =E9 par), Accounting and Science: Natural Inquiry and Commercial Reason, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, (1996a), p. xi-xviii. Bruno Latour (1996b), 'Do scientific Objects Have a History? Pasteur and Whitehead in a Bath of Lactic Acid', Common Knowledge, vol. 5(1), p. 76-91. Bruno Latour Der Berliner Schl=FCssel, Erkundungen eines Liebhabers der Wissenschaften Akademie Verlag, Berlin (traduit par Gustav Rozler), (1996). Nick Lee et Steve Brown (1994), 'Otherness and the Actor-Network: the Undiscovered Continent', American Behavioral Scientist, vol. 37(6), p. 772-790. Michael Lynch, Art and Artifact in Laboratory Science A Study of Shop Work and Shop Talk in a Research Laboratory., Routledge, London, (1985). Annemarie Mol et John Law (1994), 'Regions, Networks, and Fluids: Anaemia and Social Topology';, Social Studies of Science, vol. 24(4), p. 641-672. Ilya Prigogine et Isabelle Stengers, La nouvelle alliance, m=E9tamorphose d= e la science, Gallimard/Bantam, Paris/New-York, (1979). Michel SERRES, HERMES. LITERATURE SCIENCE PHILOSOPHY., The John Hopkins University Pr, Baltimore, (1983). Michel Serres, Statues, Fran=E7ois Bourin, Paris, (1987). Michel Serres, Conversations on Science, Culture and Time with Bruno Latour= , The University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, (1995). Isabelle Stengers, L'invention des sciences modernes, La D=E9couverte, Pari= s, (1993). --- Date of this contribution: 2 May 1997 Last Update: 2 May 1997 by Olaf Boettger --- # distributed via nettime-l : no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a closed moderated mailinglist for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@icf.de and "info nettime" in the msg body # URL: http://www.desk.nl/~nettime/ contact: nettime-owner@icf.de